Training for
Morality
By Martin L.
Cowen III
This essay discloses the object of moral training. We are several steps into new moral territory. We are excited about it.
Larry Woods (a member and Trustee of the Fellowship of Reason) keeps us on our intellectual toes. Larry drives our effort to discover new moral paths. He urges caution as we take new ones. Thank you, Larry.
Larry Woods (a member and Trustee of the Fellowship of Reason) keeps us on our intellectual toes. Larry drives our effort to discover new moral paths. He urges caution as we take new ones. Thank you, Larry.
We read Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics as translated by Joe Sachs. Professor Sachs
taught us that a century of attempts to understand Aristotle’s ethics were
hobbled by a mistranslation of the ancient Greek phrase, to kalon. The popular modern translation is “the noble.” More
accurately, according to Professor Sachs, the meaning of the Greek phrase is
“the beautiful” in an expression such as this: the virtuous person acts “for
the sake of the beautiful, for this is the end of virtue.” (1115B, 12-13)
Aristotle intends to teach us that all ethical action aims at “the beautiful.”
Ethical actions flow from virtue. Virtue is a character trait of the excellent
man. Aristotle’s virtues are not mysterious: courage, temperance, generosity,
magnificence, magnanimity, appetite for honor, gentleness, truthfulness,
friendliness, and justice. “The beautiful” is not mysterious. It means that
same thing that we mean when we say, “She is a beautiful woman.” Simple.
Aristotle says that the goal of morality is the beautiful. That we all
recognize some relationship between beauty and morality is illustrated by
expressions like “That was a beautiful thing you did” or “Don’t be ugly.”
Larry Woods cautioned us by asking,
“Well, isn’t beauty in the eye of the beholder?
Larry is concerned, as are we all, that
morality ought not be subjective or arbitrary. The complete moral relativists
might say, “If another thinks that murder is a beautiful thing, who am I to
insist otherwise.” Or, “One person’s freedom fighter is another person’s
terrorist.”
Thus, ended our first level of inquiry.
Next, we learned that “beauty is a
perception.” By this, we mean that when we see a beautiful object, we do not
analyze the object, ponder the analysis, and then conclude that the object is
beautiful. Rather we see a beautiful sunset and it strikes us as beautiful. We
hear a beautiful song and it strikes us as beautiful. We smell a beautiful
aroma and its strikes us as beautiful. We taste a beautiful flavor and its
strikes us as beautiful. We feel and delightful cloth and it strikes us as
beautiful.
We learned that each of us has
experience and training in different areas and that we can perceive the
beautiful in areas in which we are experienced or expert.
We concluded that training is crucial to
the perception of the beautiful.
Larry Woods cautions us by asserting:
“We beg the question—“Isn’t the judgment of beauty subjective?”—by replacing
that question with the assertion that “proper training is necessary for the
perception of beauty.” Larry says that we replaced the first question about
beauty with an assertion about “proper” training, replacing the question about
“beauty” with an implicit question about “proper.”
So that is where we are today in this
essay. We want to answer Larry Woods’ newest cautionary comment by answering
the question, “Is the choice of training subjective or arbitrary?”
Let us first think about training in
general. There are hundreds, perhaps thousands, of things for which human
beings are trained. Here is a short list.
Piano
|
French
|
Doctor
|
Violin
|
Latin
|
Lawyer
|
Guitar
|
Greek
|
Pharmacy
|
French horn
|
Spanish
|
Teaching
|
Oboe
|
Mathematics
|
Football
|
Harp
|
Physics
|
Basketball
|
Ballet
|
Chemistry
|
Soccer
|
Acting
|
Biology
|
Golf
|
Voice
|
Business administration
|
Tennis
|
Gymnastics
|
Truck driving
|
Scuba diving
|
This short list can be expanded simply
by listing, for example, more languages, more careers, or more specialties
within categories. “Doctor,” for example, does not clarify M.D., D.D.S, Ph.D.,
etc. or the dozens of subspecialties within those designations.
The point to be acknowledged now is that
we have no anxiety about what “proper” training means in any of these fields.
The method for training a good lawyer is agreed upon and is virtually the same
in dozens of law schools across the United States.
A well trained lawyer can recognize a
beautiful brief by virtue of his training. A well trained pianist can recognize
a beautiful recital by virtue of her training. A well trained golfer can
recognize a beautiful round by virtue of her training as can the rest of us the
least bit familiar with golf by virtue of the golfer’s score in that round.
About these claims, there is no dispute.
While the recognition of the beautiful
in a particular field by a person experienced or expert in the field is a
perception, the expert can explain why the thing is beautiful. The explanation,
though, will not render the thing beautiful to the inexperienced. A thing is
perceived to be beautiful or it is not so perceived. One cannot be “persuaded”
into the “experience” of beauty. One “has” the experience of beauty, if one is
trained and in the presence of the beautiful.
What is “proper” training for a lawyer
is agreed upon and is not arbitrary or subjective. The extreme cynic might say,
though: “Who is to say that a lawyer who does not know the law, cannot write a
brief, cannot argue a case to a jury, and does not know how to fill out
government forms is not a ‘real’ or ‘proper’ lawyer?” How do we answer such a
question? The answer is that it is a matter of definition.
A
lawyer is defined as a person who knows the law, can write a brief, can argue a
case to a jury, and knows how to fill out government forms. If she cannot do
these things, she is not a lawyer. Therefore, the “proper” training of a lawyer
must result in the creation of a lawyer. That is what “proper” training means.
The training in question results in the creation of the object of the training.
Training is not subjective or arbitrary.
“Proper” training results in the creation of the object of the training.
We like to separate ethical action into
action involving others and action involving ourselves. If ethical action means
simply the answer to the question—“What ought I do in this circumstance?”—it
seems that ethical action can be action involving only ourselves. For example:
“Ought I eat this piece of cake or rather this nice, crisp Fuji apple?” Or,
more importantly: “Ought I choose a career doing something I love (e.g. acting), or doing something I like
much less (e.g. selling vacuum
cleaners) for more money?” One might argue that the more beautiful thing to do
is to be, for a while, the starving young artist, auditioning by day and
waitressing by night. These, too, are ethical questions.
Larry Woods is more interested in fundamental
ethical choices like “selfishness v. self-sacrifice” as the choice pertains to
other people and yourself.
Before we go there, let us hammer down
the point that enormous domains of human action have objective and widely
agreed upon training regimes. Methods of training for lawyering, doctoring,
truck driving, what have you, are widely agreed upon.
If we apply what we have learned about
training in general to the question at hand, we should ask: “What is the object
of moral training?”
Morality provides the answer to the
question: “What ought I do?” The object, therefore, of moral training is to
create an individual who can excellently answer the question: “What ought I
do?” This question, in turn, points to another question: “To what end does the
individual act, in the broadest sense?” The ultimate choice is life or death.
Ought one act to live or die? The question is easy. If one chooses to die, then
he commits suicide and all questions are answered. If one chooses to live, then
that choice provides a standard by which to judge various answers in various
contexts to the moral question, “What ought I do in order to live?” “Live” in
this context means “live well.” The alternative, “live badly” leads in the
extreme case to die. “Live well” means to flourish as a human being. Readers of
this newsletter will be familiar with this concept because members of the
Fellowship of Reason call themselves eudaimonists. We are Eudaimonists.
Eudaimonism, derived from the Greek word “eudaimonia,” means “well-being-ism.”
The moralist, therefore, must look to
human nature to determine what for a human being is “living well.” A model for
this activity is found in determining what it means for a rose (the flower) to
live well or flourish. A flourishing rose is large, robust, well formed with a
strong stem, sharp thorns, and verdant leaves in the midst of a sunny, moist
country garden. (Such a rose is beautiful.) In contrast, a rose that is not
living well or flourishing is one found in the crack of a sidewalk in August on
Fifth Avenue at 49th Street in New York City, one inch high with few
petals, no thorns, and no leaves, desiccated.
Following
the rose model, a flourishing human being is, physically, a healthy, well-fed,
well-formed individual. Unlike a rose, human beings have a mental faculty. A
flourishing human being is, mentally, happy.
We all know, therefore, what a
flourishing human being looks like. (Such an individual is beautiful.)
The moralist must then ask, “How does a
flourishing human being come into existence?” How does a beautiful human being
who performs beautiful actions come into existence?
The moralist looks to history,
psychology, anthropology, and economics for an answers to these questions.
I recently finished reading A Distant Mirror: The Calamitous 14th
Century (1987), by Barbara Tuckman. As an illustration of what not to do to
create beautiful people in beautiful human environments, a better example is
not to be found. Human population reached a Middle Ages low point shortly after
this period as the result of famine, plague, rape, pillage, and war. This
period is part of the Hundred Year’s War. A prominent feature of this time was
groups of armed men who roamed Europe killing and looting peasants and anyone
else who could not defend themselves.
It is not possible in the remaining few
paragraphs of this essay to survey history, psychology, anthropology, and
economics for further guideposts. The method is established. The moralist will
conclude from a thorough survey that a dominant feature of periods during which
human beings have flourished is HUMAN FREEDOM. These periods include Ancient
Greece during the 5th century, Rome during the period of the Good
Emperors, the Italian Renaissance, the Industrial Revolution in England, and
the Nineteenth Century in Europe and America. Freedom means the protection of
property rights under the rule of law.
The
beautiful human circumstance is freedom. The individual in the circumstance of
freedom is allowed by the social circumstances (government and cultural) to do
his work, to trade his product in voluntary transactions with others, and to
keep the products of his work and trade.
The goal of moral training then is the
human being trained for liberty. This is the meaning of a liberal education.
Such training produces ladies and gentlemen. Ladies and gentlemen are human
beings trained in and, therefore, suited for freedom. (Recall and compare the flourishing rose in the
country garden.)
To summarized, we have asserted that the
goal of moral action is the beautiful. We have asserted that the beautiful is
in the eye of the beholder. We have asserted that beauty is perceived. Beauty
is perceived by a person well trained in the domain in which the beautiful
action or thing exists. “Proper” training results in the creation of the object
of the training. The object of legal training is a lawyer. The object of
musical training is a musician. The object of moral training is a human being
who can answer the question, “How ought I live well.” Living well is determined
by an examination of history, psychology, anthropology, and economics. That
examination shows that human beings flourish under freedom. Freedom is the
protection of property rights under the rule of law. The object of moral
training is to create ladies and gentlemen, individuals suited for liberty.
Ladies and gentlemen can recognize
beautiful human action by virtue of their training.