Sunday, February 24, 2013

Sur la Beauté

Sur la Beauté
by
Martin L. Cowen III


“For the sake of the Beautiful … is the end that belongs to virtue.” Aristotle

In a previous essay, we introduced the idea that the goal of ethical action is the Beautiful. “The Beautiful as the Ethical.” The Eudaimonist March 2012. In the following essay, the idea will be elaborated with an assortment of observations on the Beautiful.

The five parts I will describe are these: Performance Art, Objectivism and Life as the standard, Being in the present, Work as directed toward the Beautiful, Aristotle on Virtue, and Thomas Aquinas on the Beautiful. These parts, I am suggesting, are related to the Beautiful and Human Action.

Ephemeral Performance Art

Lately I have marveled at the common occurrence of people rehearsing for months to present a play, Romeo and Juliette, for example, on three different performance nights. Three performances and nothing remains except a memory. A live play is completely ephemeral; the event is gone as soon as the curtain comes down. The same is true of a piano recital, a choral performance, a ballet, a symphony, or an opera. Why do people create ephemeral performance art with so short an existence? This creation of the ephemeral is, I thought, quintessentially human, without further elaboration.

Combine this reflection upon the creation of ephemeral performance art with the idea that ethical action is the Beautiful suggests to me a relationship between the two ideas. These two activities, the creation of ephemeral performance art and ethical action are in essence the same activity: human beings creating the Beautiful. In the case of performance art, the creation is a beautiful play, recital, concert, dance, or opera. In the case of ethical action, the creation is a beautiful outcome in human action. Both activities are the creation of the Beautiful.

Middle class and wealthy people, who because of their relative wealth are able to enjoy leisure, spend much of their time in the midst of the Beautiful, for example, by enjoying performance art.

[The Arts were represented in ancient Greece by the nine Muses:

Muse
Domain
Emblem
Calliope
Epic poetry
Writing tablet
Clio
History
Scrolls
Erato
Love poetry
Cithara (musical instrument)
Euterpe
Song and elegiac
Aulos (musical instrument: flute)
Melpomene
Tragedy
Tragic mask
Polyhymnia
Hymns
Veil
Terpsichore
Dance
Lyre
Thalia
Comedy
Comic mask
Urania
Astronomy
Globe and compass

I include this beautiful fact about the Muses for my own pleasure and, hopefully, yours.]

Objectivism/Self-Interest?

In the philosophy of Objectivism, life is the standard of value. Life is the goal of all ethical action.

The Eudaimonist study of beauty and ethics calls the Objectivist position into question.

Consider the virtue of courage. Courage is, for Aristotle, the first virtue. It is the first virtue discussed in the Nicomachean Ethics and it is the paradigm Aristotelian virtue. Here is Aristotle’s statement of courage:

“So one who [WHO] endures or fears what [WHAT] one ought, for the reason [WHY] one ought, as [HOW] one ought, when [WHEN] one ought, and is confident in similar ways, is courageous, since the courageous person undergoes things and acts in accordance with what is worthy and in a way that is proportionate.” Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics1115b16-20.

Aristotle goes on:

“Now the end of any way of being at work is what corresponds to the active condition it comes from, and to a courageous person, courage is a beautiful thing, and so its end is something beautiful as well, since each thing is determine by its end. So it is for the sake of the Beautiful that the courageous person endures and does things that are in accord with courage.” Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics1115b 20-25.

A common argument among Objectivist is whether “life” means “survival at any price” or whether “life” means “the good life.” I have always taken the second position, that life in the Objectivist formula meant the good life. Now I suspect that the philosophically correct answer is that life equals the good life equals the Beautiful. The standard of value and the proper goal of action is not life, but the Beautiful. Ayn Rand was an Aristotelian, but she did not have the benefit of Joe Sachs’ translation of Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics (2002). Ayn Rand died on March 6, 1982, twenty years before the publication. Joe Sachs translates the Greek phase to kalon as the Beautiful. This change from centuries of tradition makes a huge difference in the interpretation of the text. (The old translation rendered to kalon as the noble.)

An example provides a proof of this point. Most people will agree that the virtue of courage sometimes requires that one put one’s life at risk. Sometimes one must choose actual death while enacting courage. The expressions: “he had a beautiful death,” or “that was a beautiful way to die,” capture our sense of such experiences. All parents would trade their lives to save their children’s lives. It would be unseemly (ugly, not beautiful) to run away when one’s children are at risk. Even non-parents will risk and even lose their own lives in order to protect the children under the care. Witness the heroism of the teachers at Sandy Hook Elementary School in Newtown, Connecticut on December 14, 2012.

So, it seems that the Objectivist standard of value, life, might be better formulated as the Beautiful.

Meditation/Being in the Present/”OM”

Self-help books abound. A frequently recurring idea in these texts is the idea of living in the present moment. “Be here now,” I have heard said.

Meditation is an ancient practice of some interest to our present discussion of beauty. “The eternal is in the moment,” if have heard said. The sacred Hindu word is “Om” or aum. The word accompanies and facilitates meditation.

Consider that one reason for staying in the moment or for meditation is the presence of beauty in that moment. We have all experienced the awe and mystery of watching a beautiful sunset or any beautiful landscape or seascape. I remember a particular moment in Provence, France, in the night, when my wife and I, with our hosts, were walking in the hills and chanced to see down the hill into a beautiful blue pool lighted from within the water in which two young people in love were embracing. We were all wordlessly arrested by the lovely scene.

In Goethe’s Faust (Faust: A Tragedy by Wolfgang von Goethe, lines 1692 to 1707) Faust makes this contract with Mephistopheles:

Faust:

If ever I recline, calmed, on a bed of sloth,
You may destroy me then and there.
If ever flattering you should wile me
That in myself I find delight,
If with enjoyment you beguile me,
Then break on me, eternal night!
This bet I offer.

Mephisto:

I accept it.

Faust:

Right.
If to the moment I should say:

Abide, you are so fair—
Put me in fetters on that day,
I wish to perish then, I swear.
Then let the death bell ever toll,
Your service done, you shall be free,
The clock may stop, the hand may fall,
As Time comes to an end for me.

“If to the moment I should say: Abide, you are so fair.”

Faust, the scientist, did not believe in the Beautiful. In the course of the play (Faust I and Faust II) he discovers that the Beautiful does exist and he ultimately utters the fateful words.

I believe that the self-help gurus are advising us to stay in the moment, for a moment, in order to discover the beauty that might be, and that often is, there.

These common practices, meditation and living in the moment, are intimately related to the Beautiful.

Work

Medical doctors are presented with illness and injury. Their goal is to cure the illness and repair the injury. Their activity can be seen as rendering a mess (the illness or the injury) beautiful (healed). Thus, the goal of medicine is the Beautiful.

The same came be said of any profession. Lawyers are presented with legal messes, for example, a breach of contract or a broken marriage or an uncompensated injury or a criminal offense, and the lawyer’s job is to fix the mess. Even a maid, a house cleaner, has the Beautiful as the goal of her job.

Most occupations, perhaps all (?), aim at the Beautiful.

Aristotle on the Virtue of Courage

Aristotle describes the mechanism of virtue in the case of courage: “So one who [WHO] endures or fears what [WHAT] one ought, for the reason [WHY] one ought, as [HOW] one ought, when [WHEN] one ought, and is confident in similar ways, is courageous, since the courageous person undergoes things and acts in accordance with what is worthy and in a way that is proportionate.” Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics1115b16-20.

Who, what, when, where, why, and how—these are the factors must come together to count a human action as virtuous. This circumstance suggests that virtue is an art.

Aristotle goes on:

“Now the end of any way of being at work is what corresponds to the active condition it comes from, and to a courageous person, courage is a beautiful thing, and so its end is something beautiful as well, since each thing is determine by its end. So it is for the sake of the Beautiful that the courageous person endures and does things that are in accord with courage.” Aristotle’s Nicomachean Ethics1115b 20-25.


This latter comment (“for the sake of the Beautiful”) reinforces the idea that virtue is an art aimed at the Beautiful.

Virtue is therefore difficult because it is an art. Art and virtue are necessarily the products of training from youth (habituation) and a lifetime of experiences.

Integritas, Consonantia, Claritas


What is the Beautiful? St. Thomas Aquinas mentions three principles: wholeness, harmony, radiance. “Three things are needed for beauty, wholeness, harmony and radiance.”

Here is what James Joyce through his character Stephen Dedalus says about these principles in A Portrait of the Artist as a Young Man.

[Wholeness]
In order to see that basket, said Stephen, your mind first of all separates the basket from the rest of the visible universe which is not the basket. The first phase of apprehension is a bounding line drawn about the object to be appended. An esthetic image is presented to us either in space or in time. What is audible is present in time, what is visible is present in space. But temporal or spatial, the esthetic image is first luminously apprehended as self-bounded and self-contained upon the immeasurable background of space or time which is not. You apprehend it as one thing. You see it is one whole. You apprehend its wholeness. That is integritas.

[Harmony]
Then, said Stephen, you pass from point to point, led by its formal lines; you apprehend it as balanced part against part within its limits; you feel the rhythm of its structure. In other words, the synthesis of immediate perception is followed by the analysis of apprehension. Having first felt that it is one thing you feel now that it is a thing. You apprehend it as complex, multiple, divisible, separable, made up of its parts, the results of its parts and there sum, harmonious. That is consonantia.

[Radiance]
The radiance of which he [Aquinas] speaks is the scholastic quidditas, the whatness of a thing. This supreme quality is felt by the artist when the esthetic image is first conceived in his imagination. The mind in that mysterious instant Shelley likened beautifully to a fading coal. The instant wherein that supreme quality of beauty, the clear radiance of the esthetic image, is apprehended luminously by the mind which has been arrest by its wholeness and fascinated by its harmony is the luminous silent stasis of esthetic pleasure, a spiritual state very like to that cardiac condition which the Italian physiologist Luigi Galvani, using a phrase almost as beautiful as Shelley’s, called the enchantment of the heart.

This essay is a musing on the relationship between the Beautiful and Human Action. At present we have only some of the “parts.” Our views on the Beautiful are not yet “whole.” We can claim that these parts have an apparent “harmony” among them as described herein. There is, finally, a certain luminescence (radiance) here present. We approach the Beautiful, n’est-ce pas?